Consider two claims. Firstly: university is difficult, much more so than school. Secondly: at university your peer group will be much smarter than they were at school. What is the usual inference which people draw, upon hearing these two claims? From what I can tell, it’s that the first is a corollary of the second. University is difficult because suddenly one is in competition with a much larger pool of really smart people.
This is completely wrong, and the second claim—that one’s peer group at university is much smarter than at school—is only trivially true.
Let’s start with that second claim. In the British school system, we have ’sets’. Somewhere around the age of fourteen, one is placed into a set, or tier, for each subject that one is taking for one’s GCSEs (school leaving exams, essentially, towards which one studies for two years, completes coursework, and ultimately takes examinations in). The people one meets at university are generally smarter than most people at school; this is true. But if, like me, you were in the top sets, the people you meet will probably not, in general, be any smarter than your peers in those sets. This is why this claim is only trivially true. To expect one’s actual peer group—the people one works and studies around—to change much is wrong.
The first claim is that university is much harder than school. This one is true, but it’s not made true by the second claim. In fact, the real error in our inference (I say ‘our’ because I have been as guilty as anyone of making it) was to connect the two claims at all. University is harder than schools for reasons that are almost nothing to do with the intelligence of one’s peer group. University is hard because one has to do work that demands one actually take in a large amount of information and process it; because there’s a lot of work, a lot of reading; because the onus is on the student to turn up and learn stuff. All of which is really nothing to do with how smart the people in one’s seminar group are. In fact, I would argue that the smarter the people surrounding one are, the easier university is.
To carry on with the seminar group example, if there are a bunch of clever people, then the chances are better that there will be a good discussion, that you’ll learn and remember things. If all you have are a bunch of idiots who stare at their feet, shuffle nervously, and stay silent the whole time, then it’s not much fun and you’ll learn less than if people argue with you.
Ultimately, all of this is of relatively little consequence. However, what it says about the way we process certain socially-accepted ‘truths’ is both interesting and worrying. What seems to happen is that two claims are made, and made in such a way that there is an implicit connection between the two. As we’ve seen, this ‘connection’ is in fact a spurious one, a logical misstep, and one of the claims is only true when we parse its context more broadly than perhaps we ought to. And yet, such claims exert a great influence on our attitudes. Attitudes are what we act on; they are the social assumptions on which we base our projections for the future on. We are damaging our understanding and our prospects by accepting claims with such dubious provenance.
Philosophers are not sceptics. The sceptic is, if you like, a role that we play sometimes; it’s a tool we use to further our understanding, to root out false or possibly false beliefs, to firm up our epistemic foundations. No one can truly be a real sceptic all the time; there are certain things that we will believe, that we must believe, if we are to live any semblance of a life. However, if we’re not to be tripped up by the lies—or at least the falsehoods, since lying implies a level of intention I’m not sure is present—that society tells us, we need to be philosophers, to engage in scepticism and use it. Scepticism can help us understand our world better, and understanding will allow us to function better in it, succeed more, and not get sucked in by the litany of falsehoods that are seemingly endlessly repeated in our ears.
4 responses
Funny, I always assumed it was the higher workload.
SquidDNA August 6th, 2005
That’s part of it, too, but I recall having a lot of work in school; it’s just that I didn’t actually do it that often.
ionfish August 6th, 2005
Yes, but the difference is that you can get away with it in school, whereas if you don’t study now, you’re basically screwed.
Moe August 7th, 2005
…Not get sucked in by shiney fibs nor embittered by our own desire (if it is frustrated) either, eg tightrope walking.
Its interesting to me persoanlly as this (uni 2nd-3rd year) was the time I got CFIDS and that on top of the difficulty of philosphical progress (zoologists are philosophers btw!) was a bit too much to cope with. I hope you are spared such a trial :)
People say its harder to encourage people to raise their game. Maybe its a ‘white-lie’, the kind a parent tells a child to bring about a result, benevolent manipulation (is there such a thing ?) If you see through it then all is well, Santa is still a force for good, isnt he ?
At uni and apparently postgrad motivation is increasingly self generated. I think that is hard, as with socks.
The idea of competition works as a motivator which helps some people forge through difficulty with vigour. Its a duality, a phantasm, imaginary. And yet the results of competition, victory and defeat, obtaining of objectives or otherwise, are very real phenomena.
1/2p worth
booly August 8th, 2005